March 2005 rough draft: Please do not cite without permission



Download 154.65 Kb.
Page1/4
Date18.10.2016
Size154.65 Kb.
#2931
  1   2   3   4
Collision with China: Conceptual Metaphor Analysis, Somatic Marking, and the EP3 Incident

Edward Slingerland, Eric M. Blanchard, and Lyn Boyd-Judson



University of Southern California

March 2005

ROUGH DRAFT: Please do not cite without permission


I. Introduction
On April 1, 2001, an American EP-3E surveillance plane collided with a Chinese F-8 fighter jet over international waters. The collision resulted in a diplomatic impasse characterized by publicly reported negotiations over the possibility and wording of an American apology. The Chinese pilot Wang Wei was lost and the US plane was forced to make an emergency landing, without authorization, on China’s Hainan Island. Despite US President George W. Bush’s appeal for access to the plane and its US personnel, authorities in the People’s Republic of China (PRC) held the twenty-four man crew, demanding an American apology and a halt to US reconnaissance missions of the Chinese coast. This demand was met with resistance from US Secretary of State Colin Powell—the US claimed that it would not apologize because it was not at fault. Subsequent American expressions of regret were met with continued Chinese requests for an official apology. The impasse was resolved on April 11 when US Ambassador Joseph Prueher delivered an ambiguous “very sorry” letter to the Chinese Foreign Minister. This nuanced letter, which expressed regret for the loss of the pilot and the incursion into PRC airspace, allowed both sides to emphasize the most politically convenient interpretation of the text for domestic and international consumption. Despite the freeing of the crew and subsequent release of the disassembled plane, this “Collision with China,” as the New York Times headlines referred to it, demonstrated the sensitive nature of US-PRC relations, and the importance of drawing lessons for future crisis negotiations. The Hainan incident raises several important questions. Were the US and PRC working from incompatible cultural understandings of the incident, conceptualizations of the Sino-American relationship, or images of international politics more generally? What meaning did the crisis have for the participants? What values underlie each side’s approach to the negotiations?
In this paper, we approach the Hainan incident as an episode of intercultural interaction, using tools from cognitive linguistics and cognitive science, particularly conceptual metaphor theory and somatic making theory, to explore a powerful model of discourse analysis. We argue that the difficulties encountered by the US and China in dealing with this incident were grounded in their very different metaphorical conceptualizations of the situation that were deployed in order to evoke correspondingly different emotional-normative reactions. The failure to perceive these differences accurately served to fuel further misunderstandings. If the value reactions of different side of a dispute are encoded and expressed in the conceptual metaphors with which they speak and think, then inter-cultural misunderstanding will often grow out of a failure to recognize these metaphors and their function in emotional biasing. Making people—particularly policy-makers—aware of these differences might help to reduce misunderstandings. Moreover, the manner in which unanalyzed metaphors unconsciously bias and limit our perceived policy choices and reactions make the need for conceptual metaphor analysis particularly acute.
The objectives of this study can be summarized as follows:

1. To make the case for the power of conceptual metaphor and conceptual blend analysis to illuminate our understanding of intercultural communication and international relations;

2. To illustrate the manner in which emotional biasing and normative values are introduced to political debate and intercultural communication by means of metaphor;

3. To go beyond existing metaphor analyses, which focus on small samples of discourse or broad generalizations, and attempt a comprehensive, empirically-rigorous, large-scale analysis of political discourse;



4. To argue for an “embodied realist” approach to comparative cultural studies that grounds abstract cognition in what may be universal, embodied experience.


II. Theoretical Orientation
Cognitive Linguistics and Conceptual Metaphor Theory1
One of the basic tenets of the cognitive linguistics approach is that human cognition—the production, communication and processing of meaning—is heavily dependent upon mappings between mental spaces. Another is that human cognition is independent of language: linguistic expressions of cross-domain mappings are merely surface manifestations of deeper cognitive structures that have an important spatial or analog component.2 These mappings take several forms, but perhaps the most dramatic form—and the form we will be primarily concerned with here—is what George Lakoff and Mark Johnson refer to as “conceptual metaphor,” where part of the structure of a more concrete or clearly organized domain (the source domain) is used to understand and talk about another, usually more abstract or less clearly structured, domain (the target domain). “Metaphor” understood in this manner thus encompasses simile and analogy as well as metaphor in the more traditional literary sense. Conceptual metaphor theory argues that our primary and most highly structured experience is with the physical realm, and the patterns that we encounter and develop through the interaction of our bodies with the physical environment therefore serve as our most basic source domains. These source domains are then called upon to provide structure when our attention turns to the abstract realm. The most basic of these structures are referred to as “primary schemas” that come to be associated with abstract target domains through experiential correlation, resulting in a set of “primary metaphors.” Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 50-54 provide a short list of representative primary metaphors (derived from Grady 1997) such as Affection is Warmth, Important is Big, More is Up, etc., specifying their sensorimotor source domains and the primary experience correlations that give rise to them.
Traditional theories usually portray metaphor as a relatively rare and somewhat “deviant” mode of communication thrown in to add rhetorical spice, but one fully reducible to some equivalent literal paraphrase. Metaphor understood in this way is thus viewed as a purely optional linguistic device. An important claim of the cognitive linguistics approach to metaphor is that metaphor is, in fact, primarily a matter of thought, not language, and that conceptual metaphor is ubiquitous and unavoidable for creatures like us. While abstract concepts such as “time” or “death” may have a skeleton structure that is directly (i.e., non-metaphorically) represented conceptually, in most cases this structure is not rich or detailed enough to allow us to make useful inferences. Therefore, when we attempt to conceptualize and reason about abstract or relatively unstructured realms, this skeleton structure is fleshed out (usually automatically and unconsciously) with additional structure provided by the primary metaphors derived from basic bodily experience, often invoked in combination with other primary schema to form complex metaphors or conceptual blends. When primary or complex source domains are activated in such cases and mapped onto the target domain, most aspects of the source domain conceptual topology—that is, inference patterns, imagistic reasoning pattern, salient entities, etc.—are preserved, thereby importing a high degree of structure into the target domain.
To give an illustration of this process, consider the question of how we are to comprehend and reason about something as abstract as “life.” Lakoff and Johnson (1999: 60-62) note that, when reasoning or talking about life, English speakers often invoke the complex metaphor, A Purposeful Life is a Journey, which provides them with a schema drawn from embodied experience. This schema is based upon two primary metaphors —Purposes are Destinations and Actions are Self-Propelled Motions—that have become a part of our conceptual “tool-box” through experiential correlation. When these two primary metaphors are combined with the simple fact (derived from our common knowledge of the world) that a long trip to a series of destinations constitutes a journey, we have the complex metaphor schema, A Purposeful Life is a Journey, which Lakoff and Johnson map as follows:

Journey  Purposeful Life

Traveler  Person Living a Life

Destinations  Life Goals

Itinerary  Life Plan

The Purposeful Life is a Journey metaphor arises out of our basic embodied experience and gives us a way to think and reason about this abstract “entity,” which in itself is unstructured and therefore difficult to reason about. As Lakoff and Johnson note (1999: 62), the full practical import of a metaphor such as this lies in its entailments: that is, the fact that the metaphoric link between abstract life and a concrete journey allows us to draw upon our large stock of commonplace knowledge about journeys and apply this knowledge to “life.” So, for instance, we unconsciously assume that life, like a physical journey, requires planning if one is to reach one’s destination, that difficulties will be encountered along the way, that one should avoid being side-tracked or bogged down, etc.


As we can see from this example, a single complex, conceptual metaphor structure can inform a whole series of specific linguistic expressions. This is a crucial proposition of cognitive linguistics: that metaphorical expressions are not simply fixed, linguistic conventions but rather represent the surface manifestations of deeper, active, and largely unconscious conceptual structures. This means that a metaphoric structure such as A Purposeful Life is a Journey exists independently of any specific metaphoric expression of it and can thus continuously generate new and unforeseen expressions. Anyone familiar with the A Purposeful Life is a Journey schema can instantly grasp the sense of such metaphors as dead-end job or going nowhere upon hearing them for the first time and can also draw upon the conceptual schema to create related but entirely novel metaphoric expressions. A country singer might write a song entitled, “The Airplane of Life Is About to Depart the Gate, and I Don’t Have a Boarding Pass,” which draws upon the A Purposeful Life is a Journey image schema but employs it in an entirely novel (albeit somewhat painful) linguistic expression.
Scholars studying metaphor from a cognitive perspective cite several types of phenomena as evidence that metaphors in fact represent conceptually active, dynamic, language-independent structures. Lakoff and Johnson 1999: 81-89 review some of the linguistic evidence, which includes “novel-case generalization,” the ability to comprehend entirely novel linguistic expressions by drawing upon a shared conceptual structure; polysemy, the fact that we find systematically related meanings for single words or expressions such as "dead end" or "lost"; historic semantic change in Indo-European languages, which suggests that conceptual metaphors such as Knowing is Seeing have been active in the minds of speakers of these languages (Sweetser 1990); and inference patterns—that is, the fact that reasoning patterns from well-structured source domains (physical travel, for instance) are commonly used to draw conclusions about abstract target domains (e.g., life). In addition, a growing body of psychological and neuroimaging studies are bolstering the case for the cognitive reality of metaphor schemas. These include spontaneous gesture studies (McNeil 1992); priming experiments (Gibbs & Colston 1995, Gibbs 1994 , Boroditsky 2000, 2001); forced-choice and free form drawing tasks (Richardson et al. 2001); and predictions of the image-schematic structure of various concepts (see review in Gibbs 2003). On the neuroimaging side, several recent fMRI studies have suggested how cognitive mappings are neurologically instantiated in the brain (see Rohrer 2004, more). All of this convergent evidence suggests that conceptual metaphor is not only a very real phenomenon but is an inevitable part of embodied human cognition.
Over the last decade in particular there has been an increasing appreciation of the promise of conceptual metaphor analysis for the fields of international relations and political science.3 It is common to recognize that the foundational thinkers of political science such as Thomas Hobbes denied and claimed to eschew the use of metaphor even while they depended on it for their arguments (Miller, 1979; Chilton, 1996). George Lakoff’s work is largely responsible for the extension of cognitive metaphor theory to the study of politics and the discipline of political science. Lakoff applied conceptual metaphor theory to US domestic politics in Moral Politics: What Conservatives Know that Liberals Don’t (1996), an effort to describe the conceptual system behind conservative and liberal worldviews, and has also written on the 1991 Gulf War, where he argues that a system of metaphors structured and defined the situation and thus guided American actions against Iraq (Lakoff 1991). Inspired in part by Lakoff, research into metaphors in IR has taken up the metaphorical dimensions of post-Cold War security in both the academic and policy realms of IR. Chilton and his co-authors have adopted a “cognitive interactive” account of metaphor to illustrate how metaphors can become contested as their underspecified entailments are formulated in different linguistic and political contexts (Chilton and Ilyin, 1993; Chilton and Lakoff, 1995; Chilton, 1996). David Mutimer (1997) has argued that in the immediate post Cold War era, the reformulation of security in terms of the metaphor of proliferation, by foregrounding “the technological and autonomous aspects of a process of spread” served to hide Western agency and responsibility for the “spread” of nuclear weapons (203). Michael Marks (2001) interrogates the metaphorical underpinnings of the “Prisoner’s Dilemma,” (PD) a model foundational to “game theoretic” approaches to IR in which mistrust among prisoners is taken as analogous to the interactions of states (c.f. Chilton and Lakoff, 1995: 45-48; Lakoff and Johnson, 1999: 513-538). Another scholar building on Lakoff’s analysis, Tim Rohrer (1995), focuses attention on the metaphors used by President H.W. Bush to construct the post Iraqi invasion pre-US involvement situation. Though at an early stage, the literature treating metaphor in IR offers the building blocks of an intercultural approach to metaphorical political rhetoric, focusing on how metaphors function in international politics to systematically “highlight” some aspects of international relations while “hiding” others. Our project is intended to build on these advances in a systematic and empirically informed way, while incorporating insights from conceptual blending theory and neuroscience, which we turn to in the next section.
Conceptual Blending and the Recruitment of Emotions
A more recent development in cognitive linguistics is mental space and blending theory, originally developed by Gilles Fauconnier and Mark Turner. Blending theory encompasses conceptual metaphor theory, but goes beyond it to argue that all of human cognition—even literal and logical thought—involves the creation of mental spaces and mappings between them. In this way, it serves as a kind of grand unifying theory identifying conceptual metaphor as merely one particularly dramatic cognitive process (a single- or multiple-scope blend) among many more pedestrian processes, such as categorization and naming. It also goes beyond linguistic production to describe the manner in which novel motor programs, technological interfaces, and social institutions are created through a process of space blending.4
One of Fauconnier and Turner’s insights is that many expressions that seem to be simple source to target domain mappings (what they call “single-scope” blends, equivalent to Lakoff and Johnson’s conceptual metaphors) are in fact “double-scope” blends, where structure from both of the invoked domains are selectively projected to a third, blended space. In our analysis of the EP3 incident below we will, for the sake of simplicity, use Lakoff and Johnson’s notation, treating all of the metaphors we discuss as simple source to target domain mappings—in most cases, a perfectly accurate first approximation. We wish to raise the issue of double-scope blends, however, because these provide a particularly clear illustration of a phenomenon too often overlooked both within cognitive linguistics and in the broader field of political discourse analysis: the role of emotion in human reasoning and decision-making processes.
Fauconnier and Turner argue that, in many double-scope blends, the purpose of invoking the more concrete domain is to “achieve human scale”—to compress a situation with perhaps diffuse temporality, complex causality, or many agents into a single scene that is easy to visualize. Consider, for instance, their classic example of a double-scope blend, the expression “digging one’s own financial grave” (Fauconnier and Turner 2002: 131­–133), which involves blending two spaces, “Death and Dying” and “Unwitting Financial Failure.” Although at first glance this may seem like a standard source to target domain projection (with grave digging serving as a template to structure our understanding of financial decision-making), Fauconnier and Turner point out that most of the important structural features of this blend—such as agency, causality, and intentionality—come from the “Unwitting Financial Failure” space. That is, in literal grave digging one does not normally dig one’s own grave, one could not be digging a grave without being aware that one was doing so, and completing one’s grave could not the direct cause of one’s death. It is in fact the financial decision-making space that is giving the blend this structure: in making a series of bad investments one is both the agent and recipient of one’s actions, one can be making financial decisions without being aware of the consequences, etc. Fauconnier and Turner argue that the point of recruiting the “Death and Dying” space to the blend is to achieve an image that has “direct perception and action in familiar frames that are easily apprehended by human beings” (2002: 312; emphasis added), which is accomplished by giving the blend tight compression, such as one type of action versus many different types of action, a short time-frame versus extended time-frame, etc. In other words, the single vivid image of “digging your own grave” allows one to have a clearer grasp of both what one has been doing in the investment arena and what the consequences of this behavior might be.
In considering this blend at more length, however, one might wonder precisely how urgent the need to achieve human scale is in this situation. Although not ideally human scale, the process of financial decision-making is not terribly abstract or complex, and human beings seem perfectly capable of reasoning about it literally. This concern is heightened by the fact that, in this blend, all of the relevant intellectual decision-making information—agency, intentionality, causality—is coming from the “Unwitting Financial Failure” space, which makes it puzzling why one would need to involve “grave digging” at all in one’s deliberations. “Grave digging” not only contributes nothing to the abstract structure of the target of the blend (financial decision making), but in many respects is also actively incompatible with it in terms of agency, intentionality, and causality. Drawing upon “grave digging” as an input to the blend, despite its potential usefulness in creating a slightly tighter compression, would thus seem at first glance to be profoundly maladaptive if the point is simply better apprehension of the situation.
This puzzling feature is characteristic, upon analysis, of many single- and double-scope blends (for the sake of simplicity, we will refer to both interchangeably as “metaphors” or “metaphoric blends” in our discussion). This suggests that, in many cases, the primary purpose of employing a metaphor in order to achieve human scale is not to help us intellectually apprehend a situation, but rather to help us to know how to feel about it.5 The apparently clumsy choice of “grave digging” as a metaphor for financial decision making becomes decidedly less so when we think of its recruitment as designed, not to provide tighter structure per se, but rather to import the negative, visceral reactions inspired in human beings by graves, corpses, and death into the blend. For instance, consider what it would mean for someone to understand each of her financial decisions as shovelfuls of earth, making her financial grave that much deeper and bringing her that much closer to financial death. The point seems to be to get the listener to “live in the blend” by associating the unpleasant visceral connotations of a frightening grave being dug deeper and deeper into the earth with, for instance, each additional purchase she makes of Cisco Systems stock. The author of the metaphor might even help the imaginative process along by imitating the noise of damp earth accumulating in a pile beside a grave (“thump, thump!”) and pantomiming the movement of a shovel as his friend sits at a computer making these (in the view of the blend-creator, at least) ill-considered purchases with the click of a mouse. The purpose here is not necessarily to help the recipient of the metaphor to better apprehend the situation intellectually—she presumably already knows that she has lost a lot of money on Cisco, and that the stock price is not likely to recover anytime soon—but rather to help her know how to feel about it, to convey a sense of impending doom and thereby goad her into making the decision to immediately cease her current activities. The creator of the metaphor has a very particular normative position to communicate (continued investment in Cisco is bad), and attempts to communicate this judgment through the exploitation of powerful negative emotions. If the metaphor is accepted by the recipient, the choice is clear: no one wants to end up in the grave. This highlights a feature of metaphorical blends that is not always emphasized: they are not simply normatively neutral devices for accurately apprehending situations, but are in fact often created and communicated in order to advance particular normative agendas, which they accomplish through the stimulation of predictable visceral reactions.
We can see this even more clearly in another metaphor discussed by Fauconnier and Turner, that of a senator accused of “snatching food out of the mouths of hungry children” by vetoing an aid bill (2002: 313). They argue that the point of this particular metaphor is to achieve human scale and help the listener apprehend the situation: the vetoing of the bill and its causal implications are somewhat abstract, long-term and indirect—not at all at a human scale—whereas snatching food from children is an immediately comprehensible scene. Again, though, the point seems to be not so much to allow the listener to understand more clearly, but rather to inspire them to feel a certain way: to feel anger, revulsion, and a righteous desire to stop or remedy the situation. The metaphor thus serves a polemic purpose, communicating a particular normative orientation by recruiting predictable human emotions: any undamaged human agent will be gripped by revulsion and anger at the sight (or imagined sight) of food being snatched by a powerful, well-fed adult from the mouth of a hungry, helpless child. If we accept the metaphor, we are then committed to feeling anger and revulsion concerning the senator’s vote. By the same token, supporters of the senator’s policy will dispute the accuracy of the metaphor, no doubt suggesting alternate framings of the situation—for instance, by vetoing the aid bill, the senator is in fact helping dependent Third World peoples learn how to “stand on their own feet”.

We believe that that this emotive-normative function has been somewhat overlooked in most previous discussions of metaphoric blending: such metaphors do guide reasoning, often in very particular directions chosen by the creators of the metaphor, but often by means of inspiring normativity-bestowing emotional reactions. This is why conceptual metaphoric blending is arguably the primary tool in political and religious-moral debate, where human scale inputs are recruited polemically in order to inspire somatic-emotional normative reactions in the listeners.6 Acceptance of the validity of the metaphor inevitably commits the listener to a certain course of action (or, at least, a potential course of action), and this effect can be reliably predicted by the metaphor author because of the relatively fixed nature of human emotional-somatic reactions. This argument is essentially an attempt to connect the insights of cognitive linguists with those of neuroscientists who argue for the importance of somatic states and emotional reactions in human value-creation and decision-making.


Emotions and Human Cognition: The Somatic Marker Hypothesis
In the last decade there has been an explosion of literature on the role of emotions in human reasoning in such fields as behavioral neuroscience, cognitive science, and philosophy.7 In the interest of brevity, we will focus on one well-known representative of this trend, Antonio Damasio. In his breakthrough work, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (1994), Damasio argues that—pace Descartes and the Enlightenment model of the self—emotionally-derived and often unconscious feelings of “goodness” or “badness” play a crucial role in everyday, “rational” decision-making. In what Damasio refers to as the Enlightenment “high-reason” view of decision-making, the individual considers all of the options open to her, performs a cost-benefit analysis of each option,8 and then coolly chooses the rationally optimal option. Damasio argues that this model is implausible simply because there are so many options theoretically available at any given moment, and the human mind is not capable of running simultaneous analyses of all of the theoretically possible courses of action. Therefore, the body contributes by biasing the reasoning process—often unconsciously—before it even begins.
This point is vividly demonstrated by cases described by Damasio where damage to the prefrontal cortex, a center of emotion processing in the brain, severely impairs an individual’s ability to make what most people would consider “rational” decisions. Although the short- and long-term memories and abstract reasoning and mathematical skills of these patients were unimpaired, in real-life decision-making contexts they were appallingly inept, apparently incapable of efficiently choosing between alternate courses of action, taking into account the future consequences of their actions, or accurately prioritizing the relative importance of potential courses of action. Interestingly, when their decision-making processes are examined closely, these patients appear to approach something like the “high reason” ideal: deprived of the biasing function of somatic markers, they seem to attempt to dispassionately consider all of the options theoretically open to them, with the result that they become paralyzed by indecision, fritter away their time on unimportant tasks, or simply commit themselves to what appear to outside observers as poorly considered and capriciously selected courses of action.9 Revealingly, despite his almost complete real-life incompetence, the patient referred to as “Eliot” scored quite well on the Standard Issue Moral Judgment Interview—developed by the Kantian moral psychologist Lawrence Kohlberg, and which measures a person’s ability to abstractly reason their way through moral dilemmas and other theoretical problems. This theoretical ability to reason about dilemmas did not, however, translate into an ability to make actual reasonable decisions: “at the end of one session, after he had produced an abundant quantity of options for action, all of which were valid and implementable, Eliot smiled, apparently satisfied with his rich imagination, but added, ‘And after all this, I still wouldn’t know what to do!’” (1994: 49) Damasio postulates that this statement, as well as Eliot’s inability to make effective decisions in real-life situations, can be attributed to the fact that “the cold-bloodedness of Eliot’s reasoning prevented him from assigning different values to different options, and made his decision-making landscape hopelessly flat” (1994: 51).
Less dramatically, the theory of somatic marking explains why human beings are often such bad —i.e., not rationally ideal—decision-makers, especially when operating in something other than their ancestral environment.10 Dispassionate calculation makes it clear that we are likely to achieve a much better payoff investing $20 weekly in some conservative mutual fund rather than using that money to buy lottery tickets, but the reasoning processes of many are (incorrectly, in this case) biased by the powerfully positive somatic marker attached to the image of the multi-million-dollar payoff. Similarly, the powerfully negative image of a jetliner falling in flames from the sky prevents many from making the “rational” decision to fly rather than drive, even though commercial airline travel is demonstrably much safer than automobile travel. While navigating by means of powerful, reasoning-biasing somatic markers must have been adaptive in our dispersed, hunter-gatherer “environment of evolutionary adaptation” (EEA), it sometimes leads us into errors of judgment in the more complex world of settled agricultural societies, especially when modern technology is thrown into the mix. Despite these potential drawbacks, however, somatic marker biasing seems to have played a crucial role in the survival and flourishing of creatures such as ourselves. “All emotions have some kind of regulatory role to play, leading in one way or another to the creation of circumstances advantageous to the organism exhibiting the phenomenon”, Damasio notes. “Emotions are about the life of an organism, its body to be precise, and their role is to assist the organism in maintaining life” (1999: 51). This insight into the role of emotion in human reasoning serves as an important corrective to the Enlightenment ideal of disembodied reason, as well as to approaches in international relations and political science that adopt an overly rationalist perspective.
Integrating Damasio’s insights with those of cognitive linguists, one might argue that a primary function of creating metaphoric blends is to harness emotions produced by “basic-level” scenarios and recruit them in order to facilitate or influence the direction of decision-making in more complex or abstract scenarios. The manner in which this is accomplished is the projection of somatic images, along with their accompanying somatic markers. These markers are probably relatively fixed for organisms such as ourselves—darkness, pollution, and physical debility are always marked with negative emotions and therefore felt as “bad”—and this is what one would expect from evolution: potential ancestors infused with warm, fuzzy feelings at the sight of putrefying meat were quickly taken out of the gene-pool. The ability of the human mind to perform conceptual blending, however, means that these relatively fixed “human scale” visceral reactions can be recruited for a potentially infinite variety of purposes, including the conscious exploitation of somatic markers by skilled rhetoricians in order to advance their own agendas.
Of course, the claim that emotional reactions play a large role in political discourse is by no means a new one—it has a long history that can be traced from Aristotle’s Rhetoric through Plato, Hobbes, Descartes, Hume and Adam Smith (Marcus 2000). The role of affect has, however, been relatively neglected by International Relations theory, inhibited as it is by the dominant assumption of rationality (Crawford 2000).11 Moreover, as we hope to demonstrate below, conceptual metaphor and blending theory provide us with a clear and effective methodology for documenting and analyzing precisely how basic-level emotions are recruited to bias attitudes towards more abstract or complex situations.


Download 154.65 Kb.

Share with your friends:
  1   2   3   4




The database is protected by copyright ©ua.originaldll.com 2024
send message

    Main page