Afterword: Analytic Philosophy and its Others



Download 84.05 Kb.
Page1/2
Date13.06.2017
Size84.05 Kb.
#20434
  1   2
Afterword: Analytic Philosophy and its Others

The purpose of this Afterword is to take up the topics broached at the end of the penultimate section of the General Introduction to this volume. It was observed there that during the third quarter of the twentieth century there was a tendency among analytic philosophers to oppose “Continental philosophy” to “analytic philosophy”. In this way of speaking the former term was meant to function in roughly the way the term “sophistry” once did for Socrates – as a name for the very kind of thing that serious philosophy is not. This, in turn, had the effect of allowing the term “analytic philosophy” to function as a synonym for serious philosophy. It was also remarked there that this tendency – and the correlative tendency sharply to mark off analytic philosophy from other kinds of philosophy – is no longer as pronounced among analytic philosophers as it once was. It was suggested that this change has been accompanied by two further related changes, one having to do with analytic philosophy’s attitude toward the history of philosophy more generally and another – yet more recent one – having to do with its attitude more specifically towards its own history. The purpose of this Afterword is to discuss these three dimensions of change in analytic philosophy’s attitudes toward its supposed philosophical others – its philosophical neighbors, the philosophical past, and its own past – and to remark upon their implications for its still-evolving self-understanding of itself as a distinctive tradition of philosophy in its own right.


I. The Distinction between Analytic and Other Kinds of Philosophy

Russell Russell in a number of his writings singled out the French philosopher Henri Bergson as a prime example of his philosophical opposite – a non-analytic philosopher – the kind of thinker who encourages the cultivation of instincts, tendencies and desires which interfere with the cultivation of the sorts of intellectual virtues required for what Russell deemed to be genuinely philosophical investigation. The interest of Bergson lay in the way in which he could be taken to represent an unusually frank proponent of an entire tendency in philosophy which Russell sought to oppose – and of which Hegel, Nietzsche, and the American pragmatists were Russell’s three other favorite examples. (For more on Russell’s critique of Bergson, see the Note on Russell in this volume.) Something in this opposition between two kinds of philosophy – which Russell first sketched in the second decade of the twentieth century – has proven to be a remarkably enduring fixture of the tradition, at least until recently. Russell’s critique of Bergson was in service of articulating a distinction between appropriately hard-headed philosophers and comparatively soft-headed philosophers – a distinction which, however inchoate, has played a continuing role in shaping analytic philosophy’s understanding of its philosophical other, as well as in shaping certain controversies which have in recent years increasingly come to dominate the internal discourse of analytic philosophy itself.

Many analytic philosophers today might well be willing to admit that they are in no position to specify the conditions which philosophical work must satisfy in order to count as “analytic” or genuinely “hard-headed”, while also being passionately concerned to retain their right to enter the charge that the work of some particular author be deemed unworthy of an analytic philosopher – as being insufficiently rigorous or overly soft in some respect. On what basis is this sort of judgment made? Those who make it are likely to insist that they simply can tell a work of analytic philosophy when they see one. Conversely, they can just tell when someone is no longer producing analytic philosophy, even if the work in question is authored by someone who was previously considered (and still considers herself) to be an analytic philosopher. That is, they can tell when a certain tipping point has been reached – when too many of the virtues of such philosophy have fallen away, or when too many of the vices characteristic of the writings of French or German “Contintental” luminaries obtrude themselves, or when there is a bit of both. This can lead to impassioned denunciations – episodes in which one analytic philosopher accuses another putative member of the guild of having betrayed a communally shared conception of the philosophical calling.

Yet even when such intramural denunciations are made (and they are no longer as infrequent as they once were), questions naturally arise about whom the denouncer is speaking for and how the legitimacy of the charge is to be adjudicated. Consider the following remarks by Crispin Wright, made in the context of the closing remarks of a review of John McDowell’s Mind and World:

If analytical philosophy demands self-consciousness about unexplained or only partially explained terms of art, formality and explicitness in setting out of argument, and the clearest possible sign-posting and formulation of assumptions, targets, and goals, etc., then this is not a work of analytical philosophy....At its worst, indeed, McDowell's prose puts barriers of jargon, convolution and metaphor before the reader hardly less formidable than those characteristically erected by his German luminaries.....[T]he stylistic extravagance of McDowell's book – more extreme than in any of his other writings to date – will unquestionably color the influence it will exert...[T]he fear must be that the book will encourage too many of the susceptible to swim out of their depth in seas of rhetorical metaphysics.  Wittgenstein complained that, "The seed I am most likely to sow is a certain jargon."  One feels that, if so, he had only himself to blame.  McDowell is a strong swimmer, but his stroke is not to be imitated.

Crispin Wright is one of the leading analytic philosophers of the present day. John McDowell’s Mind and World is arguably one of the single most influential works of analytic philosophy of the past quarter of a century. Or, perhaps we should say, in order not to beg a question here: It is arguably one of the single most influential works of the past quarter of a century written by someone who, at least for most of his career, was deemed by at least most of his contemporaries, to be a practicing analytic philosopher. Perhaps, with the publication of this book, John McDowell suddenly ceased to be an analytic philosopher; perhaps Crispin Wright was the first to publicize the fact of McDowell’s exodus from the community. Yet the relevant passages in Wright’s text read less like a report of an astonishing discovery (news flash: McDowell has emigrated to a different philosophical continent!) and more like a plea for an edict of excommunication (proposed motion: respect due a member of our community no longer to be accorded to McDowell!). But on what grounds is such a charge entered and before which tribunal? And how is its validity to be determined?

Wright need not have had a clear view of how such questions are to be answered in order to feel that he is, nonetheless, in the right – and about something important. He is evidently writing, even here in this part of this review, as someone who is not without considerable admiration for McDowell’s abilities as a philosopher. Yet he is also writing from a sense that some line has been crossed in McDowell’s latest work; so that this product of philosophy, by this erstwhile analytic philosopher, is one which has gone too far. It is important to make clear that, once a work of philosophy has reached the point where it looks and sounds like this, then (as Wright bluntly puts it) “this is not a work of analytical philosophy”.

Notice that the fundamental ground of the criticism, at least in the above passage, appears in the first instance not to lie in a charge directed against either the character of the doctrines McDowell upholds or the method of philosophy which he practices. The charge is quite explicitly directed at the style of the work. Apparently a work which courts such a style may no longer be counted as analytic philosophy. Some of the vices of style are linked by Wright to features which analytic philosophers in the past have often regarded as characteristic of “Continental” efforts at philosophizing (fuzziness of thought, liberal employment of metaphors, extravagance of expression). Other aspects of the vicissitudes of McDowell’s style are linked by Wright to more time-honored complaints – familiar already to Socrates – leveled against forms of philosophy which are feared because of their potential to win a following (to corrupt the youth, inspire imitation, and lead the next generation astray).

This can readily lead to a situation in which two sets of readers, equally familiar with the philosophical temperament of the reviewer, are drawn to opposite conclusions: One set, upon reading such a review, concludes that the work is one with which they need not bother further (given that it permits itself such forms of stylistic license); whereas the other concludes, against the reviewer’s own intentions, that the work might well be of philosophical interest (just because the danger it appears to pose to this reviewer is of this sort). It is a noteworthy feature of analytic philosophy in its most recent Anglophone phase that increasing numbers of philosophers who regard themselves as members of “the analytic tradition” have in this way often become more concerned to differentiate themselves from certain others who also so regard themselves than they are to differentiate themselves from any current species of non-analytic philosopher. Just as in the aftermath of the Russian revolutions both Stalin and Trotsky were far more able to tolerate a temporary truce with Churchill or Roosevelt than either was to tolerate one between themselves; so, too, there are now sub-communities of analytic philosophers who find it far easier to enter into non-aggression pacts with those who are simply outsiders to their internecine quarrels than they are to make peace with those within their community whom they view as having placed themselves beyond the pale of respectability through the character of their thought or writing.

The remarks in the preceding paragraphs about certain features of the most recent phase of Anglo-American analytic philosophy are far less true of the current dispensation of analytic philosophy on the European Continent, On that side of the English Channel, where the position of analytic philosophy as a dominant tradition of philosophizing has been far less secure, one still encounters frequent attempts (undertaken by figures on either side of the mutually contested terrain) to draw bright red battle-lines between the analytic and non-analytic ways of doing things. A visiting Anglo-American analytic philosopher suddenly finding herself amidst a diverse gathering of European philosophers may be left with the impression that she has stepped into a time machine: The dominant ideological struggles (along with other aspects of how the respective German, French, or Italian dispensations of analytic philosophy currently define themselves) may strike her as a surreal recapitulation of a whole series of episodes from the past of her own tradition, only now all compressed into a single episode.

One particular recent development within the Anglophone analytic tradition has therefore been greeted with particular dismay in such combatively-minded Continental European analytic circles: A minority of influential figures within the Anglo-American analytic community have become increasingly vocal in their expressions of annoyance at efforts (by both proponents and critics of the analytic tradition) to make too much of the idea that there is a philosophically significant contrast to be drawn between analytic and other kinds of philosophy. There are milder and more vitriolic manifestations of this annoyance. At the mild end of the spectrum, there is a tendency to regard the supposedly fundamental distinction between “analytic” and “Continental” philosophy as merely indicating differences in philosophizing traceable to contingencies in the environing conditions under which philosophy evolved among different groups at different times and places. On this view, convincing historical or cultural explanations of why these differences have arisen can be offered, but nothing of real philosophical interest is at stake in them.

Bernard Williams is an example of a major figure in the analytic tradition whose later writings manifest a leaning in this direction – and thus also a concern to deny that the differences in question reflect anything philosophically deep. In a characteristic passage he writes:

The contrast between 'analytic' philosophy and 'continental' philosophy is not at all an opposition of content, of interest, or even of style. Indeed, there are some differences, some of which are important, between typical examples of philosophical writing to which these terms could be applied, but these differences do not rest upon any significant basic principles. It could even be said that these terms mark a difference without a distinction.

The terms “analytic” and “continental” mark a difference without a distinction, for Williams, if the purpose to which they are to be put is to provide a philosophical account of how the very essence of the analytic way of doing philosophy must of necessity differ from that of any other way of doing philosophy if it is to retain its integrity qua analytic philosophy. If, however, the point of using this terminology is merely to mark a difference between the sorts of writing more typically found in one tradition than another, then he is perfectly willing to grant that the terms in question may helpfully be employed to indicate characteristic differences in forms of philosophical prose. What he is most concerned to deny is that the differences thereby indicated are in any way a function of a philosophically significant opposition between two fundamentally different kinds of philosophy.

Much depends here on what it means to say that there is an “opposition” between two ways of being or doing something. In discussing a not altogether dissimilar issue – one that acquired a momentary urgency at a certain juncture within the analytic tradition (having to do with whether there is an opposition between the commitment to empiricism and that to realism about universals) – Nelson Goodman suggested that the case under consideration should be thought of as akin to the opposition between being a truck driver and being a lover of ballet. The opposition between the two is certainly real enough in this respect: If one conducts a series of interviews among the relevant sorts of individuals, one might well find that these two types of personality do not overlap. But there is no inherent or necessary opposition between the two at all – for there is nothing about what it is to be a truck driver that excludes the possibility of being a lover of ballet (or vice versa). There is no underlying principle to be grasped that accounts for or generates the impossibility of bringing these two ways of being a person into some unusual (perhaps even hitherto unprecedented) form of harmony. Williams, similarly, wishes to claim that there is nothing in either of the ways of writing that predominates in each of these two traditions which requires of the practitioner of the one that he purge himself of all traces of the other. Indeed, here, too, there might be nothing in principle which stands in the way of the possibility of these two ways of going about one’s philosophical business coming together in any number of harmonious ways.

Williams represents the milder end of the spectrum of forms of annoyance at talk of the "opposition" between analytic and continental philosophy, insofar as he thinks that there is a useful purpose that can be served by locutions such as “analytic” and “Continental” (as long as one is careful not to overestimate the philosophical interest of the differences which they mark). Hilary Putnam is a major figure who has come recently to be more vehemently critical of such ways of carving up the contemporary philosophical landscape. His worry is that the continuing employment of such locutions has its own special sort of pernicious philosophical effect. In a characteristic passage, he writes:



I am concerned about certain tendencies in analytic philosophy—by the tendency to scientism, the tendency to patronize the history of philosophy, the refusal to hear other sorts of philosophy— but fighting those tendencies is not the same thing as fighting analytic philosophy. As a philosopher whose own writing is full of references to Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Quine, Davidson, Kripke, David Lewis, and others, I count myself as an "analytic philosopher" in that sense. But … I see the tendency to think of analytic philosophy as a "movement" (a tendency that has led to the creation of new—and exclusionary—associations of analytic philosophers in several European countries) as a bad thing. From my point of view, the only legitimate function for "movements" in philosophy is to gain attention and recognition for ideas that are not yet being received or which have been neglected or marginalized. Analytic philosophy has been around a long time, and it is certainly one of the dominant currents in world philosophy. Making it into a "movement" is not necessary, and it only preserves the features I have deplored. Just as we can learn from Kant without calling ourselves Kantians, and from James and Dewey without calling ourselves pragmatists, and from Wittgenstein without calling ourselves Wittgensteinians, so we can learn from Frege and Russell and Carnap and Quine and Davidson without calling ourselves "analytic philosophers." Why can we not just be "philosophers" without an adjective?
Putnam is notably more comfortable than Williams was in his late phase to count himself as an analytic philosopher. Yet Putnam has become much more wary than Williams ever was about trumpeting the supposed virtues of the analytic style or the analytic movement in philosophy. He here suggests that when analytic philosophy was still in its comparative infancy, there was a point to distinguishing sharply between specifically analytic philosophy and various other kinds – thereby drawing attention to characteristic and widely unappreciated aspects of the new way of doing things in philosophy. In an effort to undo the relative neglect or marginalization of these initial philosophical achievements, it was altogether appropriate for analytic philosophers to struggle to articulate what was distinctive in the new way of doing philosophy. Now that analytic philosophy has become one of the dominant currents of world philosophy, however, a continued insistence upon what differentiates it from other ways of doing philosophy carries dangers with it that did not threaten the earlier stages of the tradition. Putnam’s view therefore is that the modifier “analytic” (as a device for marking off a distinctive way of doing philosophy) has outlived whatever usefulness or point it may once have had, and has become counterproductive. A misplaced insistence on philosophizing in this way threatens to close off contemporary philosophers from various forms of insight, reinforces regimes of intellectual orthodoxy, and encourages philosophical narrow-mindedness and sterility.

Williams’s and Putnam’s forms of dissatisfaction here differ not only in their respective degrees of intensity, but also in their philosophical grounds. Williams’s qualms have to do with the explanatory merits of the contrast (with whether the distinction succeeds in marking a genuinely illuminating difference between two fundamentally opposed ways of doing philosophy). Putnam’s qualms have to do with the current pragmatic value of policing the border between these two ways of doing philosophy (with whether there are intellectual costs involved in the continued employment of the contrast which were not incurred when it was first introduced). These differences in their postures notwithstanding, there is a common attitude underlying both – a distrust of a contemporary tendency to call upon the distinction to carry a kind of philosophical weight that they regard it as unable to bear.

The very possibility that this attitude might be shared by a number of leading figures within the analytic tradition marks, in and of itself, a significant development within the tradition. The comparatively recent emergence of this attitude (along with the correlative capacity to approach other ways of doing philosophy in this more ecumenical spirit) is arguably related to two further transformative moments in the recent evolution of the analytic tradition. These form the next two topics of this Afterword.
II. Analytic Philosophy’s Relation to the History of Philosophy

Analytic philosophers have differed markedly in their attitudes with respect to the history of philosophy. Some major figures have wanted to understand what is essential to analytic philosophy as requiring a sharp break with the entire past of philosophy. For them, there is no longer any need or reason for philosophers to occupy themselves with the writings of figures belonging to the prehistory of analytic philosophy. Others have spoken (only slightly less immodestly) of a form of philosophical inheritance of the past in which our understanding of the very nature of the activity undergoes radical transformation. Their view is that we may continue to be concerned with philosophical writings of the past, but in a sufficiently novel manner that we will, in effect, introduce (as later Wittgenstein put it) “a kink” in the history of philosophy. Yet others have seen their own philosophical projects as directly inheriting those of the great figures in the past. Our relation to them need not require any specifically historical form of understanding of the past; it should involve nothing more than direct philosophical engagement with the writings of these “mighty dead”.

Their differences notwithstanding, these attitudes share a tendency that has characterized the thinking of many analytic philosophers when it comes to the history of philosophy. The tendency is to take it for granted that meticulous scholarly inquiry into the historical dimension of the history of philosophy requires a mode of concern with philosophical texts and figures that is fundamentally different in nature from the kind of engagement with them that ought to form the business of a serious philosopher.

Many analytic philosophers have been prone to look upon “the history of philosophy” (insofar as they even considered there to be a serious discipline bearing this title) as a particular branch of the discipline of history – a mode of inquiry involving methods, concerns, and aims fundamentally distinct from those of the philosopher. One famous analytic philosopher went so far as to hang a sign on his office door that read: “Just say ‘No’ to the history of philosophy!” This statement is unusual in its succinctness and candor, but the underlying sentiment it expresses was once not uncommon. Many analytic philosophers have felt that the history of philosophy represents an alien (even if perhaps, for some institutional reason, unavoidable) thorn in the flesh of a properly “analytic” department of philosophy.

Times have changed, and over the past few decades this attitude has gradually given way to a more generous one, according to which the history of philosophy represents a genuine philosophical discipline in its own right. It is nonetheless still seen by many as one very different from analytic philosophy proper. Even analytic philosophers who welcome those with historical-philosophical interests as their colleagues nevertheless frequently regard such interests as somehow distinct from (and quite possibly irrelevant to) those that properly ought to animate the activity of serious first-order philosophizing. In an analytic department in which this sort of attitude predominates, members of the faculty with developed historical interests may discover themselves to be, in effect, denizens of an institutional ghetto. The intellectual space in which their inquiry proceeds is permitted to adjoin, but deemed to be by no means integral to, that of the philosophical community of which they are nominally a part.

But this, too, is changing. Analytic philosophers today, for a variety of reasons, are increasingly inclined to regard the very idea of a department of philosophy lacking capable historians of philosophy as existing in a condition of impoverishment. One set of concerns that play a role here comes from those practitioners of analytic philosophy (and there have always been some) who look upon their philosophical questions as stemming directly from those of a broader philosophical tradition. They have good reason to regard those who seek to acquire a broader and deeper understanding of that tradition as colleagues engaged in a form of inquiry continuous with their own.

This sort of connection to the community, however, can still leave the historian of philosophy (rightly) feeling that the reigning conception of the distribution of labor presupposes a historically parochial perspective on the philosophical bearing of the past on the present. For even among analytic philosophers who have in this way been open to the philosophical importance of cultivating such forms of familiarity with ancient, medieval, or early modern texts, there sometimes still lingers a tendency to regard the proper purview of the professional historian of philosophy as coming to an end at that moment in the history of the subject when the analytic tradition begins. On this way of looking at things, philosophers like Frege, Russell, Carnap, Wittgenstein, and Quine are to be regarded as forming a part of “our” analytic-philosophical present in a way that no merely “historical” figure could. One is thus thought to be doing a special sort of philosophical violence to such authors if one treats them as fit subjects of “historical” inquiry.

Conversely, it has not been uncommon for those trained as professional “historians of philosophy” to view the manner in which even their comparatively sympathetic analytic colleagues take up the ideas of the great figures of the past as evincing a peculiarly ahistorical relation to the history of philosophy. This quarrel, which has been conducted throughout the history of the analytic tradition, between card-carrying analytic philosophers and their historically scrupulous professional colleagues, has had a number of different aspects. There is something to be said for and against each of the parties in this quarrel.

Speaking first in defense of the analytic philosopher, it should be noted that it is by no means evident that these tensions are to be traced solely to an usual degree of hostility on the part of analytic philosophers towards the philosophical past. They may be a function of very different ways of engaging with the past – among which the attitude of the typical analytic philosopher towards prior tradition may in fact represent the more time-honored alternative, far more closely resembling the ongoing philosophical activity of past historical epochs than is generally conceded by the contemporary working historian of philosophy. On this account of the matter, the source of tension enters into the practice of philosophy not through what is strange in the analytic philosopher’s attitude towards the history of philosophy, but rather through what is in fact historically quite parochial in the attitude of the contemporary historian towards the history of philosophy: namely an insistence on the cultivation and maintenance of a certain form of historical self-consciousness.

The form of self-consciousness at issue here was first introduced into the history of philosophy comparatively recently, by the interpretive tradition, just over two centuries ago. Its arrival on the analytic scene is a far more recent – and hence all the more unsettling – event. The irony underlying this line of defense is that the source of the conflict is thus attributed to a respect in which analytic philosophy is actually more traditional in its approach to philosophical problems (precisely in its not requiring the cultivation of historical self-consciousness in order to get down to philosophical business). Or, at any rate, it is far more traditional in its mode of philosophizing than the contemporary historian of philosophy hostile to analytic philosophy has usually been prepared to acknowledge.

There has been, and still is, a strongly cultivated tendency within analytic philosophy to approach the writings of the great figures of the past, as nearly as possible, as if they were attempting to make direct contributions to current debates, and to treat “the mighty dead” not just as philosophical equals but as philosophical contemporaries. Grice famously remarked that we “should treat great but dead philosophers as we treat great and living philosophers, as having something to say to us”. Such an approach to the history of philosophy hardly constitutes an unprecedented form of philosophical engagement with the past. In commenting on how best to understand Plato’s concept of an Idea, Kant sums up a longstanding method of engaging with the great figures of philosophy’s past – which he takes to permeate the writings of his great predecessors, such as Aristotle (in his relation to Plato), Aquinas (in his relation to Aristotle), and Leibniz (in his relation to all three). Here is how Kant puts it:

I shall not engage here in any literary enquiry into the meaning of the expression. I need only remark that it is by no means unusual, upon comparing the thoughts which an author has expressed in regard to his subject, whether in ordinary conversation or in writing, to find that we understand him better than he understood himself. As he has not sufficiently determined his concept, he has sometimes spoken, or even thought, in opposition to his own intention.


The interpretive ideal here is to understand a philosophical author better than he understood himself. On the modern historian’s conception of what it is to grasp a philosophical author’s intention, the first order of business is to overcome hindrances introduced by intervening episodes in the history of philosophy – episodes which necessarily obstruct our view of the original intention. On the traditional understanding of the interpretive ideal – to which Kant here gives eloquent expression – the intervening history of philosophy is an indispensable aid in fully determining the author’s concept. (For that might well require forms of philosophical proficiency unknown to the original author.) There is much in the contemporary analytic philosopher’s way of inheriting this traditional ideal that might be irritating to the working historian of philosophy. Nevertheless, the fact remains that the prevalence among contemporary analytic philosophers of a version of this mode of engagement with past philosophy cannot be attributed solely to an unprecedented benightedness in analytic philosophy’s relation to the philosophical past.

Bernard Williams puts the point well in the following passage, regarding the relation that almost all philosophy has had to at least certain portions of its past – most notably, to Plato and Aristotle:

The involvement of Greek philosophy in the Western philosophical tradition is not measured merely by the fact that ancient philosophy originated so many fields of enquiry which continue to the present day. It emerges also in the fact that in each age philosophers have looked back to ancient philosophy—overwhelmingly, of course, to Plato and Aristotle—in order to give authority to their own work, or to contrast it, or by reinterpretation of the classical philosophers to come to understand them, and themselves, in different ways. The Greek philosophers have been not just the fathers, but the companions, of Western philosophy. Different motives for this concern have predominated in different ages…. But from whatever motive, these relations to the Greek past are a particularly important expression of that involvement in its own history which is characteristic of philosophy and not of the sciences…. [W]e might say that the classical philosophers Plato and Aristotle are classics in the sense that it has been impossible, at least up to now, for philosophy not to want to make some living sense of these writers and relate its positions to theirs, if only by showing why they have to be rejected.
Nevertheless, it is one thing to view certain philosophers as having the status of living classics in this sense (so that it is impossible for the practicing philosopher not to want to make some living sense of their writings). It is another and much more problematic matter to insist that the terms in which that task of making sense is to be achieved are fully specifiable prior to such a philosophically sustained encounter with the past. Williams’s target here is the attitude towards the history of philosophy famously summarized in Ryle’s frequent injunction to treat something written by Plato as though it had just come out in the most recent issue of Mind. The advocate for the professional historian of philosophy might well be able to argue that the attitude towards the past expressed in that injunction is at best naïve and at worse historically obtuse.

One reason this quarrel is no longer quite as heated as it once was is because there has recently been a surprising amount of fruitful intellectual interchange between the original parties to the dispute. Some of the recent attempts on the part of scholars trained within the analytic tradition to read major figures of the philosophical past – and, in particular, to read them as far more sympathetic to some particular contemporary analytic project than one might have supposed possible – have occasioned fascinating and influential monographs. They not only have given rise to further historical scholarship on these figures, shaped by them, but also have led analytic philosophers to rethink aspects of their original readings of these figures.

These analytically informed revisionist readings and re-readings of the history of philosophy have played a part in the analytic tradition’s gaining an increasingly historically informed perspective on its own place within the broader sweep of the history of philosophy. It is now more widely acknowledged than it once was that the analytic tradition is in fact one philosophical tradition among others – rather than a development that culminates and so stands above and beyond the history of philosophy. Contemporary analytic philosophers have begun to recognize that their tradition has nourished stereotypes about its differently minded (non-analytic) neighbors that were as uninformed as they were dismissive, regarding them as, for example, sloppy and overwrought. Their disparaged counterparts have been only too ready to return the disfavor, with equally uncomprehending and dismissive slurs (of which “fussy” and “boring” have been among the more polite).

Encouraged by individual efforts at perestroika stemming from each side, there are signs of a gradual thaw in this philosophical cold war. These stereotypes have increasingly come to be regarded as equally prejudicial and uncomprehending on both sides. There has, non-coincidentally, come to be a surge of historical scholarship investigating the ways in which, throughout the history of the analytic tradition, there have been important junctures at which analytic philosophers sought to engage in fruitful dialogue with interlocutors outside their tradition. (To name only three notable examples which have attracted recent scholarly attention on both sides of the Atlantic: Frege’s influential correspondence with Husserl, Ryle’s sympathetic review of Heidegger’s Being and Time, and Rawls’s late dialogue with Habermas.) The tendency to view such episodes as merely momentary thaws in the cold war has now given way to an interest in the various ways in which the two traditions may have repeatedly cross-fertilized one another in the past – and (even more importantly) how they may continue to do so, for as long as their philosophical identities remain sufficiently distinct to permit such forms of intellectual commerce to be mutually enriching.

As the analytic tradition entered the last quarter of the twentieth century and moved into the twenty-first, its resistance to the idea that it represents only one continent in the larger world of philosophy (rather than as a movement with a rightful claim to dominate the whole of that world) began to fade. This has helped to transform not only its attitude toward its neighbors as a matter of contemporary philosophical practice, but also its attitude toward itself. A correlative shift has taken place within analytic philosophy in recent decades in the way in which the relation between its philosophical past and its present is conceived. This shift has taken place along a number of dimensions. One aspect of it is the present frequency with which analytic philosophers now seek to enrich their own tradition, and contribute to its further evolution, by working self-consciously to incorporate this or that philosophical line of thought or intellectual strategy drawn from another tradition – in some cases, a contemporaneous one, in others an early modern one, or one that goes back as far as Plato and Aristotle. The beginnings of this development were already occurring in the 1950s (in the work of figures such as Sellars, Strawson, Elizabeth Anscombe and Peter Geach). By the 1980s it had become a commonplace to speak of movements and strands within analytic philosophy such as those of analytic Aristotelianism, Thomism, Pragmatism, Kantianism, Hegelianism, and even analytic Marxism.

As we have noted above, Bertrand Russell, writing in the middle of the twentieth century, was happy to combine the terms “analytic” and “empiricism” into the novel compound “analytic empiricism”, using the first term to designate what was new in the form of philosophy he was championing and the second term to identify an older strand in the broader philosophical tradition that he sought to inherit, transform, and carry forward. If one had told him that soon there would be philosophers who purported to belong to a tradition that was built in part upon his own early work, but who would describe their philosophical outlook using compound expressions such as those just mentioned, he would have been mystified – and, in some cases, dismayed. For Aristotelianism, Thomism, and the rest, were among the very movements in philosophy he was vigorously fighting to displace in favor of his own conception of philosophy as logical analysis. The early Russell would have had difficulty comprehending how the term “analytic” in these different compounds could have anything to do with what he had originally meant by it, and so could amount to anything more than a mere homonym in relation to his own use of it. He could not have foreseen the development of a tradition that would both draw inspiration from the analytic philosophers of his generation and also seek to reincorporate so much that he himself was determined to eliminate. More generally, from that early vantage point, it would have been impossible for anyone to make out how a tradition might develop out of the work of Russell and the other early analytic philosophers that would be robust and capacious enough to be able to retain its distinctive identity, while reincorporating so many aspects of the previous strands of philosophy that the founders had sought to vanquish.

These two forms of interest in the philosophical past – first, the longstanding interest on the part of analytic philosophers in the classic authors of the philosophical tradition (such as Plato, Aristotle, and Kant), and second, the far more recent resurgence of interest in figures previously excluded from the canon (such as Hegel and Marx) – have been further nourished by, as well as themselves, in turn, contributing to the cultivation of yet a third kind of interest in analytical philosophy’s relation to the past, more specifically a new kind of interest in its own past.


Directory: blogs
blogs -> Ap u. S. History presidents list the Young Republic, 1788-1815 George Washington, 1789-1797
blogs -> Sci-145: Introduction to Meteorology Lecture Note Packet 3 Chapter 9: weather forecasting
blogs -> Critical Kent: The Topographies Project: Beaches (2015). Background notes for Explorations of: From Whitstable into the Thanet Coast
blogs -> Atlantic Basin and eastern Pacific they are called hurricanes
blogs -> Anbookstore com Copyright 2013
blogs -> Kin 465 – Interculturalism, Health & Physical Activity Glossary of Terms
blogs -> The St. Louis Cardinal’s Miracle Run At the beginning of September, no one would have guessed that the St. Louis Cardinals would be playing in the World Series, let alone making the playoffs
blogs -> The St. Louis Cardinal’s Miracle Run At the beginning of September, no one would have guessed that the St. Louis Cardinals would be playing in the World Series, let alone making the playoffs

Download 84.05 Kb.

Share with your friends:
  1   2




The database is protected by copyright ©ua.originaldll.com 2024
send message

    Main page